Constructible hierarchy: Difference between revisions

no edit summary
No edit summary
 
(4 intermediate revisions by one other user not shown)
Line 2:
 
== Definition ==
Say a subset \(X\) of \(Y\) is definable if there are some \(z_0, z_1, \cdots, z_n \in Y\) and some formula \(\varphi\) in the language of set theory so that the elements of \(X\) are precisely the \(x\) so that \(Y\) satisfies \(\varphi(x, z_0, z_1, \cdots, z_n)\). For example, under the von Neumann interpretationdefinition of ordinal, the set of even numbers, the set of odd numbers, the set of prime numbers, the set of perfect squares greater than 17, and so on, are all definable. Using elementary cardinal arithmetic, youthere can note that thereare \(\max(\aleph_0, |Y|) = |Y|\) definable subsets of an infinite set \(Y\), and thus "almost all" subsets of an infinite set are not definable. The parameters \(\vec{z}\) aren'tare of importance inwhen the\(Y\) contextis ofuncountable, definableto subsetsensure ofthat thethere naturalare numbers,more sincethan all\(\aleph_0\) elementsdefinable subsets of the\(Y\), naturalbut numbersthey aredo definable,not buthave theyany willeffect be ifwhen \(Y\supseteq\mathbb N\) is uncountablecountable, becausesince noall uncountableelements beof pointwisethe definable,natural andnumbers ensure that there aren't just always \(\aleph_0\)are definable subsets of a set.
 
Like with the von Neumann hierarchy, the constructible hierarchy is built up in stages, denoted \(L_\alpha\).<ref>K. J. Devlin, "[https://core.ac.uk/download/pdf/30905237.pdf An introduction to the fine structure of the constructible hierarchy]" (1974)</ref>
Line 12:
Note that this is a cumulative hierarchy, and thus the [[reflection principle]] applies.
 
This is always contained in the respective rank of the von Neumann hierarchy: \(L_\alpha \subseteq V_\alpha\). This can be shown by a transfinite induction argument. It initially completely actually agrees with \(V\): all subsets of a finite set are definable, therefore \(L_\alpha = V_\alpha\) for \(\alpha \leq \omega\). However, while \(V_{\omega+1}\) is uncountable, there are (as we mentioned) only countably many subsets of a countable subset, and thus \(L_{\omega+1}\) is countable and a proper subset of \(V_{\omega+1}\). In general, \(|L_\alpha| = |\alpha|\) for \(\alpha \geq \omega\).<ref>Most set theory texts</ref>
 
If \(\kappa = \beth_\kappa\), then \(|L_\kappa| = |V_\kappa|\). However, the existence of a \(\kappa > \omega\) so that \(L_\kappa = V_\kappa\) (they're equal, not just equinumerous) is independent from the axioms of \(\mathrm{ZFC}\), if they're consistent. This is because some models of \(\mathrm{ZFC}\) think it's true, and others think it's false, thus the completeness theorem applies.